ethical truth, essay paper, English homework help

+44 222 444 1122

Give us a call

11 Vancouver St, London

Get direction

ethical truth, essay paper, English homework help

Description: https://www.studypool.com/images/sp_logo@2x.png

Top of Form

search

Bottom of Form

  • Homework Q&A
  • Sell Docs
  • Become a Tutor
  • Login
  • Sign Up
Description: https://www.studypool.com/img/icons/topNavbar/all.png

All Subjects

arrow_drop_down

Description: https://www.studypool.com/img/icons/topNavbar/bus.png

Business

arrow_drop_down

Description: https://www.studypool.com/img/icons/topNavbar/hum.png

Humanities

arrow_drop_down

Description: https://www.studypool.com/img/icons/topNavbar/mat.png

Mathematics

arrow_drop_down

Description: https://www.studypool.com/img/icons/topNavbar/pro.png

Programming

arrow_drop_down

Description: https://www.studypool.com/img/icons/topNavbar/sci.png

Science

arrow_drop_down

Description: https://www.studypool.com/img/icons/topNavbar/wri.png

Writing

arrow_drop_down

Access over 20 million homework & study documents

Top of Form

search

Bottom of Form

  • Home >
  • Humanities >
  • ethical truth, essay paper, English homework help

ethical truth, essay paper, English homework help

Content Type

User Generated

User

anggl

Subject

Humanities

Description

Assignment Details:

Topic:

Explain and give examples of the three paths to ethical truth: emotion, reason, and intuition.

  • Clearly declare a stance/thesis in introductory paragraph
  • Two full pages are required
  • Cover page and reference page required
  • APA formatting is required
  • Two pieces of support from the week’s material are required: https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=qGMg3w_FC3c,https://hondros.adobeconnect.com/_a1008268392/ethical-decision-making/  

Supporting your work:

Use at least two pieces of information from this week’s assigned material to support your work. You have an option to supplement your work with additional material if needed, which must be from scholarly sources (i.e., peer-reviewed journal articles, books, etc.). Wikipedia is not a credible source.

All direct quotations and information taken from your sources must be credited using APA Style®. Resources on APA Style® may be found in the Hondros Library by clicking the “APA Resources” link on the left navigation.

1 attachments

Slide 1 of 1

  • Description: https://www.studypool.com/img/icons/open_in_full-24px-min.png

psychology, in part because a wealth of empirical data suggests that it offers a descriptively correct account of moral judgment (Nado, Kelly, and Stich n.d.). The fact that Pascal is an important early-modern proponent of ethical intuitionism has not been recognized in this literature. Pascal’s status as an overlooked forebearer of ethical intuitionism should not exhaust contemporary interest in his moral philosophy, however. His most important contribution to ethical theory lies in his account of how and why we fail to live up to our ethical intuitions. 2. The Imagination Bestows Value The preceding analysis raises an important question. If the heart produces immediate moral sentiments, and if those sentiments are both true and compelling, then why does anyone ever act immorally? Why do we not always act in accordance with our sentiments? Pascal’s response to this question leads directly into his famous critique of the imagination. Even though our moral sentiments have the felt sense of truth, according to Pascal, we are also strongly motivated to believe Self-Deception and Wrongdoing in Pascal’s Pensées 363 that our imaginative fantasies are true. If it is the heart that responds to the perceived value of moral goods, it is the imagination that bestows value on them in the first place. As a result, even though we do respond immediately to moral goods, we typically perceive those goods only after they have already been filtered through a haze of imaginative fantasy. Early on in the Pensées, Pascal launches what is arguably the sharpest attack on the imagination in Western intellectual history.11 He calls it the “dominant faculty in man,” and even goes so far as to say that it has established a second human nature in each person (L44/ S78). In its war with reason, the imagination is the “master of error and falsehood” because its products are not always false and so are even more insidiously duplicitous: the imagination sets “the same mark on true and false alike” (L44/S78). Moreover, Pascal notes that far from being immune to its seductions, intellectual sophisticates are the most vulnerable to them: “I am not speaking of fools, but of the wisest men, among whom imagination is best entitled to persuade. Reason may object in vain, it cannot fix the price of things” (L44/S78). To say that the imagination can, and reason cannot, “fix the price of things” is to give the imagination the power to bestow value (Maguire 2006, 17–21). Because it has this power, it would appear that the imagination can satisfy virtually any desire. Pascal himself suggests that the imagination can satisfy the desire for domination, knowledge, and pleasure (in other words, the “triple concupiscence” of 1 John 2:16, discussed in fragments L545/S460 and L933/S761). In each of these spheres, the imagination asserts its power to create objects of value: Imagination has its happy and unhappy men, its sick and its well, its rich and poor; it makes us believe, doubt, deny reason; it deadens the sense, it arouses them; it has its fools and sages, and nothing annoys us more than to see it satisfy its guests more fully and completely than reason ever could. Those who are clever in imagination are far more pleased with themselves than prudent men could reasonably be. They look down on people with a lofty air; they are bold and confident in argument, where others are timid and unsure. . . . Imagination cannot make fools wise, but it makes them happy, as against reason which only makes its friends wretched: one covers them with glory, the other with shame. . . . Imagination decides everything: it creates beauty, justice and happiness which is the world’s supreme good [L44/S78]. The imagination can satisfy the desire for power and domination (the clever in imagination “look down on people with a lofty air . . .”); it can 11 To date, the best treatment of Pascal’s account of the imagination is Ferreyrolles 1995, which emphasizes the relationship (discussed below) between the imagination and custom. See also Ferreyrolles 2002, an article-length précis of this work. 364 Journal of Religious Ethics satisfy the desire for knowledge (the imagination “makes us believe, doubt, deny reason”), and it can satisfy the desire for bodily pleasure (it “deadens” and “arouses” the senses, and it “creates beauty”). Pascal also seems to imply that from a subjective point of view, imaginary satisfaction is no different from real satisfaction. It does not really matter whether I am superior to someone else—imagining that I am feels just as good. The imagination makes fools happy because it allows them to desire objects that are not real, conjure up groundless pleasures, and invest real objects with more value than they can bear. One such object is the self. True to his Augustinian roots, Pascal focuses on the self as the primary object that is imaginatively invested with excessive value. Pascal calls the imagination a “proud power” (superbe puissance) and regards it as the handmaiden of pride (L44/ S78).12 How else could the self “make itself the center of everything” (L597/S494) except by imagining that it is? A real person faces indefeasible limits; only an imaginary person can seem like a god. Although Pascal usually focuses on the way we excessively magnify the value of our own selves, any object may be imaginatively invested with more value than it can bear: one may build up a fantasy about a commodity (a new car, for example), a specific self-understanding (of oneself as being just the kind of dashing person who would drive such a car), or some other pursued goal (making enough money to buy the car). The possibilities are endless. In each case, however, the perceived value of the object sought is a function of how it is imaginatively construed. 2.1 Custom and the social imagination So far, Pascal’s indictment of the imagination is severe, but it remains squarely within our own thought-world. That is, we can map Pascal’s critique onto our own contemporary understanding of “the imagination” and see why he criticizes its power. Yet recent scholarship has shown that according to Pascal, the imagination does more than allow us to dream up wishful, self-serving fantasies. The imagination also shapes our spontaneous experience by functioning as a socially constructed repository for our dispositions and tacitly held values. As a result, the faculty of imagination is internally related to the body, custom, and habit. As John D. Lyons puts it, the Pascalian notion of custom is so closely linked to the imagination that the two forces are two facets of the human condition. One appears to be more concerned with action 12 “Arrogant force” is Krailsheimer’s translation of “superbe puissance.” “Proud power” is a better translation, because it captures Pascal’s associative link between the imagination and the sin of pride (superbia). Self-Deception and Wrongdoing in Pascal’s Pensées 365 (custom) and the other with perception (imagination), but they act together, strengthening each other. What we have the habit of doing shapes what we see, and vice-versa [2005, 99]. For example, Pascal’s major critique of the imagination also includes this initially puzzling description of a wise and dignified magistrate who reacts badly to an odd-seeming preacher: Would you not say that this magistrate, whose venerable age commands universal respect, is ruled by pure, sublime reason, and judges things as they really are, without paying heed to the trivial circumstances which offend only the imagination of weaker men? See him go hear a sermon in a spirit of pious zeal, the soundness of his judgment strengthened by the ardor of his charity, ready to listen with exemplary respect. If, when the preacher appears, it turns out that nature has given him a hoarse voice and an odd sort of face, that his barber has shaved him badly and he happens not to be too clean either, then, whatever great truths he must announce, I wager that our senator will not be able to keep a straight face [L44/S78]. Pascal’s phrase at the end of this passage ( je parie la perte de la gravité de notre sénateur) suggests that the magistrate is so struck by the preacher’s lack of decorum that he loses control of his own body and laughs involuntarily.13 This is certainly an amusing scene, but it is somewhat curious that Pascal blames the magistrate’s behavior on his imagination. After all, the magistrate does not dream up a vivid yet false scenario to distract himself from the preacher’s message. There is no suggestion that, in truth, the indecorous preacher does not have an odd face, a hoarse voice, and so on. Thus, it would seem to make more sense for Pascal to blame the magistrate’s behavior on the faculty of sensation, or the will. For instance, he might say that vividly concrete sensations impede the magistrate’s grasp of abstract truth, or that his will errs in failing to assent to the truth because it is distracted by considerations that are rationally irrelevant. Instead, he criticizes the imagination. Notice, however, just what it is about the preacher that so shakes the magistrate’s composure. The magistrate is struck by the preacher’s shabby, indecorous, and unseemly demeanor. In the relevant context, there is nothing inherently humorous about a hoarse voice or an unkempt appearance. Indeed, these qualities might be thought to inspire reverent awe instead of laughter. They might be taken as proof that the preacher is a genuinely holy man who is properly contemptuous of the world’s secular values, for example. This is not the 13 My analysis of the social aspects of the imagination depends heavily on Moriarty 2003a. See also Ferreyrolles 1995. 366 Journal of Religious Ethics magistrate’s reaction at all. So the question remains: why does the magistrate laugh, and why does Pascal blame his laughter on the imagination? Surely the magistrate laughs at the preacher because the magistrate has internalized the customary values of his wider social world. His concern for decorum shows that he has internalized the values of his society, and that his unreflective reaction to the preacher is a product of a lifetime of habituation and training. When he looks at the preacher, he sees what he has been trained to see. Myriad social pressures—his family life, his concern for his self-image, his political and economic interests, and so on—have collectively shaped his character and turned him into someone who laughs at a preacher with “a hoarse voice and an odd sort of face.” Presumably, however, the magistrate does not explicitly regard himself as the kind of person who mocks and ignores the unsophisticated. He does go to hear the preacher “in a spirit of pious zeal . . . ready to listen with exemplary respect,” after all. Nonetheless, his behavior shows us what he really values—not truth, but decorum. He is so struck by the preacher’s lack of decorum that he cannot stifle his own laughter. Moreover, the fact that his reaction is spontaneous and bodily suggests that he holds these values tacitly. We can assume that if asked, the magistrate would not explicitly assent to a claim like, one should not pay attention to people who appear disheveled. However, the magistrate’s behavior shows that he does believe it. His body expresses the underlying beliefs and values that he would never explicitly avow. The fact that he manifests them physically and not reflectively shows that they subsist at a level beneath his explicit awareness. He has internalized them so thoroughly that, in Pierre Bourdieu’s phrase, they are “inscribed on his body.”14 In short, Pascal claims that the imagination shapes the way we perceive moral goods because it serves as the repository for both personal and social values. The imagination is personally constructed because it can be altered by our own behavior; in this sense, its deliveries are the product of those personal dispositions and values that we have, over time, embraced and reinforced, until they have hardened into habit. Yet the imagination is also socially constructed 14 Bourdieu, in speaking of the submission to “symbolic violence”—his version of ideology—writes, “This submission . . . is itself the effect of a power, which is durably inscribed on the bodies of the dominated, in the form of schemes of perception and dispositions (to respect, admire, love, and so on), in other words beliefs which make one sensitive to certain public manifestations, such as public representations of power. It is these dispositions, in other words, more or less what Pascal puts under the heading of ‘imagination’ which dispense ‘reputation’ and ‘glory’, give ‘respect and veneration to persons, works, laws, the great’ ” (2000, 171; my emphasis). Self-Deception and Wrongdoing in Pascal’s Pensées 367 because it is the point of intersection between our personal values and the customary dispositions and values of our wider social milieu. The personal and social aspects of the imagination are dynamic and mutually reinforcing. To return for a moment to contemporary ethical theory, Pascal’s account of the socially constructed imagination reveals that he is not just an ethical intuitionist but a social intuitionist. A social intuitionist recognizes that people are “intensely social creatures whose moral judgments are strongly shaped by the judgments of those around them” (Haidt 2001, 828). While some moral intuitions may be innate to everyone, social intuitionists claim that people acquire most of their particular moral intuitions through custom and habituation—that is, through their participation in thick cultural webs of moral practice. Once again, although social intuitionism currently enjoys pride of place among empirically oriented moral psychologists, there has been no recognition that Pascal is an early advocate of its central claims. 3. How Moral Reasoning Goes Wrong: Self-Deception According to Pascal, moral judgments are spontaneous responses to perceived moral values, and the deceptive faculty of imagination bestows value on moral goods. It is no surprise, therefore, that Pascal also thinks that our moral reasoning is highly vulnerable to selfinduced error. By “moral reasoning,” I mean the ex post facto deliberation that often follows spontaneous moral judgments of the heart. Pascal claims that even when our moral sentiments are veridical, we often reject those sentiments as a result of self-deceptive moral reasoning. Accurate moral reasoning requires that our spontaneous moral sentiments be veridical. There is no guarantee that our sentiments are veridical, however. Worse, they can seem veridical even when they are not. As a result, we can easily mistake false fantasies for truthful sentiments. All our reasoning comes down to surrendering to sentiment. But fantaisie is like and also unlike sentiment, so that we cannot distinguish between these two opposites. One person says that my sentiment is mere fantaisie, another that his fantaisie is sentiment. We should have a rule. Reason is available but can be bent in any direction. And so there is no rule [L530/S455]. Whereas a sentiment comes from the heart, a fantaisie comes from the imagination. But from the subjective point of view, it can be difficult to distinguish between the two. A veridical sentiment and a false fantaisie both come with the same self-certifying warrant of felt truth. When one 368 Journal of Religious Ethics tries to distinguish between them, one has recourse only to reasoning, which is highly vulnerable to the persuasive power of imaginative fantasy. As a result, we often treat false, self-serving fantaisies as if they were veridical sentiments. Furthermore, this error—treating false fantaisies as veridical sentiments—is often far from innocent, according to Pascal. Indeed, it is most often a willful mistake, which means that the central threat to the moral life is not just error but self-deception. In fragment L975/ S739, Pascal succinctly outlines his account of how the imagination affects moral reasoning: “Men often take their imagination for their heart, and often believe they are converted as soon as they start thinking of becoming converted.”15 To take the imagination for the heart is to self-deceptively believe that one’s own self-serving fantasies reveal the felt sense of conscience. The unbeliever who falsely believes that he is converted takes his imagination for his heart when he willfully fails to discern the difference between what he merely wants to be true (an imaginative fantasy) and what he really knows to be true (a deliverance of the heart). Thus, according to Pascal, moral reasoning typically goes wrong when a moral agent persuades herself that her immoral beliefs and actions are, in fact, moral after all.16 It is useful to present a concrete example of “taking the imagination for the heart.” Consider the case of Tom, a stockbroker engaged in a scheme to defraud his clients. On Pascal’s account, when Tom is initially presented with the opportunity to participate in the scheme, he spontaneously forms a veridical sentiment (he might experience it as a “pang of conscience”) that his participation would be wrong because the scheme is illegal and immoral. He is disposed to believe this spontaneous, immediate insight because sentiments are subjectively self-certifying. At the same time, his imagination produces a range of false, exculpatory, and self-serving fantasies. These imaginative fantasies suggest ways in which his participation in the scheme would be licit after all, and so they function as temptations that incite him spontaneously to reinterpret his own immoral engagements as moral. (Perhaps he imagines himself as a latter-day Robin Hood, defrauding 15 Of course, the explicit topic of the fragment is religious conversion and not moral reasoning, but the obstacles that impede conversion are also the obstacles that impede successful moral reasoning. Moreover, even though Pascal would take care to leave room for the operation of divine grace in conversion, it is also the case that the trajectory of Pascal’s apology in the Pensées depends on his ability to present the choice to become a Christian as both a rational and a moral choice. 16 The brief sketch in this section is not intended as a complete Pascalian account of self-deception, still less as a full account of self-deception as such. For a way into the vast philosophical literature on self-deception, see Mele 2001. For a contemporary account that stresses Augustinian themes, see van Frassen 1988. Self-Deception and Wrongdoing in Pascal’s Pensées 369 his morally dubious clients as a way of providing for those who are more deserving—in other words, himself and his family.) Because the fantaisie is even more attractive than the sentiment, Tom believes the former, persists in his moral wrongdoing, and even comes to believe that his actions are morally upright. It is not hard to multiply cases like that of Tom ad infinitum. Very often, when one is faced with a morally fraught situation, what one perceives as the moral choice is relatively unattractive, but the immoral choice is highly alluring. Pascal gives us a technical vocabulary in which to describe this state of affairs, a vocabulary that is grounded in an interesting and plausible philosophical psychology. Moreover, assuming that the case of Tom seems convincingly realistic, it is an account that resonates with our own lived experience of the moral life. However, Pascal’s contribution to moral theory is more than just another technical description of moral wrongdoing. Pascal’s chief contribution is the insight that the conflict between sentiment and fantaisie is an evaluative conflict, driven by the moral agent’s response to the perceived attractiveness of competing goods. Pascal’s central claim is that in a moral dilemma, an agent usually perceives an immoral choice as more attractive than a moral choice precisely because the immoral choice is rooted in self-serving imaginative fantasy. In the example above, Tom does not participate in the fraudulent scheme as a result of a clear-eyed decision for evil (he is not a moral monster). Nor does he explicitly choose to do wrong all the while desiring to do right (he is not morally weak). Nor does he fail to understand what the moral law requires (he is not morally ignorant). Rather, his immoral choice is attractive to him because he is able to call up imaginative fantasies that allow him to quash his pangs of conscience and spontaneously reinterpret his actions as morally licit. Pascal probably would not assert that moral wrongdoing must always proceed in exactly this way. That is, I doubt that he would deny that reflective, fully self-aware moral wrongdoing is possible. Even in such cases, however, we still might want to say that moral wrongdoing includes an element of self-deception. Suppose, then, that Tom knows perfectly well that his participation in the price-fixing scheme is wrong, and suppose that he justifies his actions only by saying to himself: Ha! All this “right and wrong” stuff is for losers! Granting that Tom initially forms a veridical sentiment that his participation is morally wrong, when he later embraces the imaginative fantasy that he is somehow beyond good and evil (so to speak), he has persuaded himself of something that, as a result of his sentiment, he already knows to be false: that he is not bound by the relevant moral standard. This justification still seems like a form of self-deception. 370 Journal of Religious Ethics Thus, Pascal argues that we are highly vulnerable to self-deception as a result of the way we respond to value—in this case, to the value of different moral goods. Like any attentive student of the human condition, Pascal recognizes that under the influence of desire, people often depart from the strict canons of rationality and believe just what they want to be true. In the Pensées, he makes this point using the faculty psychology of his day: The will is one of the chief organs of belief, not because it creates belief, but because things are [that is, seem] true or false according to the aspect by which we judge them. When the will likes one aspect more than another, it deflects the mind from considering the qualities of the one it does not care to see. Thus the mind, keeping in step with the will, remains looking at the aspect preferred by the will and so judges by what it sees there [L539/S458]. Even when the mind, the locus of belief, is in a position to form correct judgments, it often does not do so because it is led astray by its own desires. The image of the mind brought up short, captivated by the charms of one aspect (face in the French) of the matter it is judging, evokes nothing so much as the rapt gaze of a lover caught in the fog of love. Like a lover so caught, the mind, believing that the object of its gaze is eminently worthy of attention, realigns its judgments of truth and falsity accordingly. Metaphorically, Pascal is making the point— now common in philosophical psychology—that desire can influence belief formation. It is therefore easy to see why we are highly likely to come to believe that our self-serving but enticing imaginative fantasies are true. Our imaginative fantasies are so enticing because we ourselves voluntarily construct them as maximally alluring. The faculty of the imagination is partly under our control, after all. Of course, sometimes we seem to be passive recipients of fantasies that wash over us unbidden, but it is equally clear that sometimes we actively, explicitly construct attractive fantasies. Moreover, even in the former case, we can usually exercise enough control to interrupt unwelcome fantasies or dismiss them from our minds, so it is still accurate to say that the imagination is under our voluntary control, in the relevant sense. In the arena of moral decision making, our imaginative fantasies give us a way to preserve an image of ourselves as morally upright and blameless, even when we are not. Because fantaisies are inherently compelling, the very activity of imagining our own moral innocence comes with built-in persuasive power that can shape our beliefs selfdeceptively. In the example above, Tom may initially realize that he is not really a virtuous Robin Hood figure, but as he continues to turn his fantasy over in his mind, reinforcing it with loving attention and Self-Deception and Wrongdoing in Pascal’s Pensées 371 psychic energy, he will soon come to believe in it wholeheartedly. Moreover, because this imaginative activity is something over which Tom has voluntary control, it seems apt to say that by steeping himself in his imaginative fantasies, he deceives himself. To return to the terminology above, in the moral arena, taking the imagination for the heart—mistaking fantaisie for sentiment—is usually a willful misconstrual. Indeed, Pascal implicitly makes this very claim in a long fragment entitled “self-love” (amour-propre): The nature of self-love and of this human self is to love only self and consider only self. But what is it to do? It cannot prevent the object of its love from being full of faults and wretchedness: It wants to be great and sees that it is small; it wants to be happy and sees that it is wretched; it wants to be perfect and sees that it is full of imperfections; it wants to be the object of men’s love and esteem and sees that its faults deserve only their dislike and contempt. The predicament in which it thus finds itself arouses in it the most unjust and criminal passion that could possibly be imagined, for it conceives a deadly hatred for the truth which rebukes it and convinces it of its faults. It would like to do away with this truth, and not being able to destroy it as such, it destroys it, as best it can, in the consciousness of itself and others and it cannot bear to have them pointed out or noticed. It is no doubt an evil to be full of faults, but it is a still greater evil to be full of them and unwilling to recognize them since this entails the further evil of deliberate self-delusion [illusion volontaire] . . . [L978/S743]. There can be no doubt that this fragment describes something that is recognizable as a project of self-deception. According to Pascal, under the influence of excessive self-love, the human self tries to hide from itself the fact that it is wretched, small, flawed, and deserving of contempt from others: “il veut etre grand, il se voit petit; il veut etre heureux, et il se voit miserable. . . .”17 In the French, Pascal’s alliterative repetition of the verbs valoir (to want) and se voir (to see oneself), draws attention to the gulf between what the self desires and what it knows to be true. The self does not just notice the gulf between what it wants and what it is, it also actively tries to hide this gulf from itself and others. It “conceives a deadly hatred for the truth which rebukes it,” and it “would like to do away with this truth,” but it cannot. Instead, it destroys the truth “in the consciousness [sa connaissance] of itself and others”—not completely, however, but only “as best it can.” This fragment is not only about self-deception, however. It is also about love, the immoderate love that people have for themselves and 17 Nicholas Hammond makes this point (2003, 244). 372 Journal of Religious Ethics their concomitant demand that others ratify that love. For Pascal, self-deception—and, by extension, all moral wrongdoing—is, first of all, an axiological blunder about the value of the self. The operative notion of value is a thick, almost Platonic conjunction of moral worth, beauty, and fulfillment. What the self desires, and knows it does not possess, is a sheen of greatness and perfection that compels the love of others. Conversely, the qualities the self does possess are, in the classical Greek sense, shameful—wretchedness, faults, and flaws that deserve only the contempt of others. Furthermore, the self’s axiological blunder is not an isolated mistake, but a form of moral perversity that infects its every engagement and facilitates tyrannical behavior toward the world at large. As he writes elsewhere in the Pensées, each person comes to think he or she is everything to everyone (L668/S547), and we all try to subjugate others when they frustrate our goals (L597/S494). We can even come to believe that we are rivals to God, the center and source of all value (L617/S510). Accordingly, the present fragment on self-love suggests that the initial question that should launch any study of moral wrongdoing is, how can we so drastically misapprehend our own value? Perhaps unsurprisingly, Pascal holds that in order to answer that question, we must advert to the fall and the noetic effects of sin. As a result of the fall, we have lost the ability to evaluate goods properly. This is why we deceive ourselves, why our imaginative fantasies are so alluring, and why we so easily slough off the demands of the moral life. 4. The Evaluative Fall So far, my presentation of Pascal has been lamentably one-sided, ignoring the fact that Pascal’s ethics is, first and foremost, a theological ethics. Moreover, no aspect of his ethics is uncolored by his understanding of the fall. Most studies treat Pascal’s account of the fall in straightforwardly conventional terms as a fall of the reason or the will.18 In my view, we may arrive at a better understanding of Pascal’s account of the fall, and thus a more complete understanding of his ethics, by looking beyond the fall of the reason and the will— understood narrowly as the faculties of calculating and choosing—to an even deeper fall, a fall in our ability to perceive and respond to value. 18 Melzer 1986 is one of the few book-length treatments of Pascal’s understanding of the fall. It offers a post-structuralist account of the fall as a “fall from truth into language.” Another is Wetsel 1981, which argues that Pascal hopes in the Pensées to demonstrate the fall’s historicity. See also Miel 1969, 66–74; and, more recently, Moriarty 2003a, 2006. Self-Deception and Wrongdoing in Pascal’s Pensées 373 Pascal himself regards the consequences of the fall as primarily axiological and affective. The fall is therefore first and foremost an evaluative fall. Certainly, Pascal does launch a variety of attacks on our rational faculties in the Pensées.19 Like his master, Augustine, Pascal clearly believes that the human will is fallen and divided.20 More importantly, throughout the Pensées, he asserts that since God alone is the infinite good, God alone is the proper object of our love: we should love God alone with unbounded love, and we should love other goods only insofar as they help us to love God. As a result of the fall, however, we have lost the ability to love God above all things. Although we retain a capacity for infinite love, we can find no infinite object in the world that answers to that capacity. We therefore strive to satisfy our infinite love with finite goods, an inevitable project inevitably doomed to failure. Pascal amplifies this traditional Augustinian account by emphasizing that our inability to love God above all things manifests itself concretely as an inability to perceive the true value of moral goods. When Pascal says that the will is “depraved,” he means that it is fundamentally oriented toward some false conception of the good, and that this basic orientation affects every concrete instance of moral perception. After all, the fundamental love that Pascal names “love of self ” or “love of God” is not just one particular emotion, attitude, or desire among others. It is more like a comprehensive orientation or stance. As such, it shapes all of one’s emotions, attitudes, and desires. When Pascal says that concupiscence automatically makes all our decisions for us because it has become our second nature, he makes this very point (L119/S151, L616/S509). A person does not wake up in the morning and say, “Today, I want to do three things—get a haircut, 19 He calls reason “corrupted” (L60/S94, L600/S497) and “impotent” (L131/S164), suggests that reason is not reasonable (L76/S111), and says that reason and the senses are engaged in mutual deception (L45/S78). In fragment L199/S230, surely one of the most important in the Pensées, he presents the human being as suspended between the twin infinities of the microscopic and the super-terrestrial, and cut off from the knowledge of either. The many fragments in which Pascal straightforwardly praises human reasoning frustrate any attempt to tie him to anti-rationalism, however. For example, he writes that reason “constitutes [our] being” (L491/S736), that “all our dignity consists in thought” (L200/S232), and that we should form beliefs on the basis of our “own inner assent and the consistent voice of [our] reason” instead of on the basis of authority (L505/S672). If Pascal condemns the reason as fallen, it is also the case that this condemnation is qualified. 20 See, for instance, fragment L502/S738: “For the will of man is divided between two principles: cupidity and charity . . . cupidity makes use of God and delights in the world, while charity does the opposite.” Sometimes, however, the two wills are presented as two natures: “Concupiscence has become natural for us and has become second nature. Thus there are two natures in us, one good, the other bad” (L616/S509). 374 Journal of Religious Ethics clean my apartment, and idolatrously love myself instead of God.” Rather, the fact that he loves himself instead of God disposes him to value certain things and reject others, to pursue certain projects and not others, and so on. It disposes him to engage with the world selfishly, no matter what he does, and so it shapes his life as a whole.21 In fact, to extend Pascal’s reflections a bit, every instance of love is the adoption of a stance. Love is always a stance because it always comes packaged, as it were, with a principle of interpretation. It orders the lover’s values and engagements by deriving them from the needs and interests of the beloved. As such, love always shapes one’s attitudes and dispositions, more or less comprehensively, depending on the nature of the beloved object.22 As Pascal succinctly writes, “the heart calls good that which it loves” (L255/S287). Throughout his writings, Pascal pursues this point by metaphorically linking love and visibility.23 In one of his most important fragments, Pascal presents a developed picture of the relationship between love, value, and perception. In fragment L308/S339, he sets up three hierarchically arrayed orders of reality—body, mind, and charity—and characterizes each with an appropriate kind of perfection, roughly described as physical power, intellectual acumen, and saintliness, respectively. The three orders of being are also three orders of value and, as such, three orders of visibility: All the splendor of greatness lacks luster for those engaged in pursuits of the mind. The greatness of intellectual people is not visible to kings, rich men, captains, who are all great in a carnal sense. The greatness of wisdom, which is nothing if it does not come from God, is not visible to carnal or intellectual people. They are three orders differing in kind. Great geniuses have their power, their splendor, their victory, their luster, and they do not need carnal or intellectual greatness, which has no relevance for them. . . . 21 Conversely, the desire to turn away from himself and back toward God is also not one desire among others. It results from conversion. He must adopt (be given) an entirely new vantage point from which everything looks different. 22 Harry G. Frankfurt puts it nicely (and sounds properly Pascalian) when he says, “Loving something has less to do with what a person believes, or with how he feels, than with a configuration of the will. . . . This volitional configuration shapes the dispositions and conduct of the lover with respect to what he loves, by guiding him in the design and ordering of his relevant purposes and priorities” (2004, 43). 23 The best discussion of the motif of sight in the Pensées is found in Hans Urs von Balthasar’s chapter on Pascal in the third volume of his theological aesthetics (1984, 179–88). Self-Deception and Wrongdoing in Pascal’s Pensées 375 Saints have their power, their splendor, their victory, their luster, and do not need either carnal or intellectual greatness, which has no relevance for them . . . [L308/S339].24 Pascal claims that denizens of each order cannot properly evaluate the goods of the other orders because they cannot see them. The “splendor” and “luster” of intellectual greatness is not visible to carnal people, he writes, because intellectual greatness has no “relevance” (the French is rapport) for them. Similarly, the absence of rapport prevents the splendor and luster of saints from being recognized by inhabitants of lower orders. Objects from outside of one’s own order seem alien and unattractive, and because one does not see them as valuable, one does not really see them at all. This is, of course, literally false, but it does point toward an important idea. To return to the language of love (for the three orders can be seen as three different stances of love), Pascal claims that I necessarily experience the world—my world—as the world that I love.25 Yet Pascal is certainly no subjectivist. The three orders are best seen as an objective hierarchy that presupposes a robust axiological and moral realism. Even if we are not always able to recognize and properly evaluate the real worth of some perceived good, its objective location on the hierarchy of goods remains in place. It is simply a feature of the world, on Pascal’s account, that it exists within a framework of objective, hierarchically ordered values. With the three orders, Pascal highlights the difference between love as a response to the inherent, pre-existing value of an object, on the one hand, and love as what invests a beloved object with value, on the other. It is natural to say that one ought to love things that are worth loving and, further, that one ought to love them in the right way.26 This insight reintroduces the key claim of the previous section, that sometimes we invest beloved objects with a value they cannot objectively bear. Thus, according to Pascal, to say that the will is “depraved,” is just to say that we have lost the ability to evaluate goods properly. Since we do not affirm that God, the universal good, is the standard of value, anything can seem like the highest good. Accordingly, Pascal delights in pointing out the bewildering array of things that philosophers, believing that their opinions are grounded in reason, have identified as the supreme good: virtue, pleasure, truth, peaceful ignorance, idleness, indifference, and more (L76/S111). Ordinary people fare no better. 24 On the point that the orders of being are also orders of value, see Mesnard 1988, 39. See Lear 1998, 132–42 for an interesting version of this idea from a psychoanalytic perspective. 26 Susan Wolf pursues this point at some length in her critique of Harry Frankfurt in “The True, the Good, and the Lovable: Frankfurt’s Avoidance of Objectivity” (2002). 25 376 Journal of Religious Ethics Pascal grants that all people naturally seek happiness but points out that no one agrees about what happiness is. Since humankind abandoned God, It is a strange fact that nothing in nature has been found to take his place: stars, sky, earth, elements, plants, cabbages, leeks, animals, insects, calves, serpents, fever, plague, war, famine, vice, adultery, incest. Since losing his true good, man is capable of seeing it in anything, even his own destruction, although it is so contrary at once to God, to reason, and to nature [L148/S181]. This is a bizarre list, to be sure, but according to Michael Moriarty, each element on it has either been the explicit object of worship by some human community, or has been sought as a form of “transcendence through transgression,” which is an implicit form of self-worship (Moriarty 2003a, 132).27 Of course, it is even easier to imagine more typical substitutes for the highest good: wealth, power, and national identity come readily to mind. In any event, the salient fact about the human will, according to Pascal, is that it tries (and fails) to invest finite goods with an infinite value that they cannot bear. Readers of the Pensées are often struck by the seemingly subjective, even relativistic, nature of some of Pascal’s thoughts about evaluating moral goods. He emphasizes that our moral judgments are perspectival, and that what seems like a firmly founded moral truth to some will seem wholly unfounded and false to others: Those who lead disorderly lives tell those who are normal that it is they who deviate from nature, and think they are following nature themselves; just as those who are on board ship think that the people on shore are moving away. Language is the same everywhere: we need a fixed point to judge it. The harbor is the judge of those aboard ship, but where are we going to find a harbor in morals? [L697/S576]. A closer reading of the Pensées suggests that, far from filing a brief on behalf of relativism, Pascal wants to lay the groundwork for identifying Jesus Christ, “the object of all things, the center toward which all things tend,” as the desired fixed point in morals (L449/S690).28 Here, however, I wish to emphasize that in our fallen state, the (apparent) 27 Moriarty does not say any more about just who it is who worshipped all these things. Further research shows that—who knew?—it was apparently commonplace of early modern thought that the ancient Egyptians worshipped vegetables, especially leeks and onions. Rampant Egyptian vegetable worship is mentioned by, for example, Thomas Hobbes (Leviathan, 4.44), David Hume (Natural History of Religion, chap. 12), and Nicolas Malebranche (The Search After Truth, 6.2.6). 28 On this point, and for a thorough exploration of Pascal’s ideas about interpretation, see Force 1989, especially 167–84. Self-Deception and Wrongdoing in Pascal’s Pensées 377 absence of such a fixed point means that we can easily exploit the perspectival character of moral truth, and even the very language with which we make moral judgments, in order to self-deceptively rationalize away our worries about our own immoral actions. In his critique of dueling in the Provincial Letters, for instance, Pascal savagely mocks the way his Jesuit opponents sanitize immoral acts by redescribing them as innocent. Jansenist and Jesuit alike agree that dueling is immoral and that defending oneself against attack is permitted. Thus, Pascal’s Jesuit innocently inquires, how could it be wrong merely to stand at an appointed spot at an appointed time? In addition, if someone else should happen by at that time and try to shoot you, well then . . . what choice do you have, really, but to defend yourself? As Pascal ironically notes, in the seventh provincial letter, “That is not really permitting the duel. On the contrary, he avoids saying that it is one, in order to make it lawful, so sure is he that it is forbidden” (Pascal 1967, 106). Under the description “fighting a duel,” I am culpable, but under the description “defending myself,” I am blameless, even though I agree that “dueling” is immoral. Without a fixed point in morals, then, our own moral language becomes a tool with which we can deceive ourselves. Furthermore, because the will has no such fixed point, and no genuine standard of value, it is buffeted by an unceasing stream of desire. That is, each person constantly experiences his own psychic life as an endless series of plastic, unstable desires that, when satisfied, immediately produce further desires. According to Pascal, our occurrent (felt) desires are instrumentally related to the incoherent project of treating finite goods as the ultimate good. Regardless of their explicit target, occurrent desires also implicitly aim at a target they cannot reach—restful happiness. Even when our desires are satisfied at the explicit level, they still fail to attain this ultimate goal. Thus, in the fullest sense, no desire is ever finally satisfied, and so humans are trapped in a state of restless longing. This constant longing is what engenders further desires: Since nature makes us unhappy whatever our state, our desires depict for us a happy state, because they link the state in which we are with the pleasures of that in which we are not. Even if we did attain these pleasures, that would not make us happy, because we would have new desires appropriate to this new state [L639/S529]. In order to stop the cycle of desire, people must be oriented toward the true fixed point in morals, God or Christ, the ultimate good. Instead of reorienting our fundamental idea of the good, however, we continue to pursue limited goods as if they were ultimate. Speaking about the universal quest for happiness, Pascal writes, 378 Journal of Religious Ethics A test which has gone on for so long, without pause or change, really ought to convince us that we are incapable of attaining the good by our own efforts. But example teaches us very little. No two examples are so exactly alike that there is not some subtle difference, and that is what makes us expect that our expectations will not be disappointed this time as they were last time. So, while the present never satisfies us, experience deceives us, and leads us on from one misfortune to another . . . [L148/S181]. People do not understand why they remain deeply unsatisfied even when their immediate desires are gratified. They fail to see that the problem lies in the fact that their desires are oriented toward comprehensive goods that are false. Suppose I believe that a successful career will bring me lasting happiness. I succeed at one job after another, all of which fail to make me happy. Pascal’s point is that I will not treat these specific experiences as falsifications of the general claim that a successful career brings lasting happiness. Instead, I will likely focus on the situational particularities of each and imagine that the general claim remains valid. (I was not happy at this job because of the boss; I was not happy at that job because of the salary, and so forth.) I exploit the fact that each situation is slightly different in order to preserve an interpretation of happiness that does nothing more than constantly engender a new set of soon-to-be-frustrated desires. As Pascal succinctly puts it, “What causes inconstancy is the realization that present pleasures are false, together with the failure to realize that absent pleasures are vain” (L73/S107). In sum, one’s felt desires and day-to-day wants are instrumentally ordered toward the satisfaction of deeper desires for more comprehensive goods. Moreover, there is a direct relationship between the way we value beloved objects and the way we see them, which affects the beliefs we form about them. Because love is always a more or less comprehensive stance toward the world, it influences the way we perceive things and thereby influences our beliefs about them. When we love something, we not only respond to its value, we also invest it with value. One way we do this is by imagining it in its ideal form—as bigger than life, wonderful, and perfect. We thereby imaginatively invest beloved objects—paradigmatically the self—with a psychic sheen that reinforces our loving attachment to them. It seems simple enough to say that we fail to evaluate moral goods properly because the will is fallen, but the point of the theory of the divided will is not just the truism that we must choose among incompatible moral goods and that we often choose poorly. The claim that our wills are incoherent is better understood as the claim that we are incoherent precisely to the extent that we cannot make sense of Self-Deception and Wrongdoing in Pascal’s Pensées 379 ourselves. The theory of the divided will therefore captures the feeling of seeming alien to oneself and the concomitant sense of puzzlement that such self-estrangement is even possible. To say that we are estranged from ourselves is just to say that our actions and our beliefs are often in fundamental conflict. Our loves and desires help shape our beliefs (see L539/S458 above). It follows that if we have incoherent desires—as we do, according to Pascal—then those incoherent desires can only shape our beliefs incoherently. Our beliefs must split along the same fault line as our wills; incoherent selves with incoherent wills can only have incoherent beliefs. The theory of the divided will, therefore, sets up a whole range of intra-psychic conflicts wherein a single human subject is wracked by action divided against action, belief divided against belief, and action divided against belief. It is no surprise, therefore, that the moral life is rife with self-deception. 5. Suggestions for Further Research This brief sketch of Pascal’s views about moral judgment and moral reasoning suggests several fruitful lines of further research. Here I will mention three. First, as I have already noted at several points, important historical and philosophical work remains to be done on Pascal’s status as a forerunner of contemporary ethical theorists. In particular, social intuitionists like Jonathan Haidt often look for inspiration from David Hume, or even Aristotle, without ever recognizing that Pascal is an even closer cousin to their own work (Haidt and Bjorklund 2008). I envision a series of focused comparisons between Pascal and contemporary ethical theorists. Ideally, such comparisons would not be purely historical. They would also allow Pascal to challenge contemporary ethicists on their own terms by revealing gaps in their thinking. For example, Pascal is able to wed his social-intuitionist ethics to a fullblooded account of moral and axiological realism, something that Haidt, at least, finds himself unwilling or unable to do.29 Second, I have focused on the perceptual and axiological aspects of Pascal’s ethics because he regards ethics and aesthetics as closely linked. Many contemporary thinkers, especially those working in the “continental” tradition, agree.30 Accordingly, Pascal provides a concrete resource from which they may draw. For example, he argues that 29 See, for instance, his interview with Tamler Sommers in The Believer, in which—at least, in my judgment—he finds himself a bit flummoxed at his inability to dismiss questions about what grounds moral truths (Sommers 2005). 30 For important foundational statements of this idea, see Gadamer 1989, 480–91; Lyotard 1994, 23–29. See also the work of Richard Kearney, especially 1995, 2003. The move to rejoin ethics and aesthetics is not confined to continental philosophy, however. See Adams 1999. 380 Journal of Religious Ethics divine grace operates on the soul by overwhelming it with aesthetic delight, which causes it to love spiritual goods over carnal goods.31 This view may resonate in interesting ways with contemporary discussions about the ethics of receptivity to the Other, or the overwhelming power of the ethical sublime. Finally, although he recognizes that the imagination is central to the moral life, Pascal’s thought challenges the sometimes facile claims of contemporary narrative ethicists and those who would look first to the “narrative imagination” for moral renewal.32 Pascal reminds us that the imagination is not just the locus of individual creative genius and speculative possibility. It is also a socially constructed repository for the (often immoral) dispositions and values of the wider world. Far from being the initial launching pad for moral critique, the imagination is often itself the faculty most in need of such critique. Furthermore, Pascal would remind us that reorienting the moral imagination is no simple matter. Certainly it is not just a matter of reading the right novels, imaginatively identifying with the right moral exemplars, or trying to dream up new possibilities for moral community. Because the imagination is socially constructed, reorienting the imagination requires something like a massive program of counter-habituation, comparable to becoming a native member of a wholly new society. In short, reorienting the imagination would require something that looks quite a lot like an ongoing program of religious conversion. Pascal therefore sounds an important note of caution about the moral possibilities of the imagination. With this article, I have tried to show that Pascal is an important moral philosopher who deserves to be studied alongside other early modern ethical theorists. For too long, English-language scholarship on Pascal has confined itself primarily to arguments about the cogency of the wager, or, at best, to discussions of his supposedly fideistic religious epistemology, but Pascal is a multifaceted thinker. He deserves to be the object of a body of scholarship that ranges as widely as his own thought.33 31 This is the delectatio victrix (victorious delight) of Jansenist Augustinianism. For language that suggests the delectatio victrix, see Pascal’s “Writings on Grace” in Levi 1995, 243 and his “On the Conversion of the Sinner” in Cailliet and Blankenagel 1948, 118–20. The source of this idea in Augustine may be found in De peccatorum meritis et remissione 2.19.33 and De spiritu et littera 1.29.5. See also Moriarty 2003b, 148; Gouhier 1986, 71–81; and Magnard 1991, 248. 32 Without a detailed engagement with the writings of others, this assertion barely rises to the level of an accusation, let alone an argument. Since I lack the space to support it, I judge it best to pass over its specific targets in silence. 33 I wrote parts of this paper as a William Rainey Harper dissertation fellow at the University of Chicago Divinity School, and I wrote the final version as a postdoctoral Self-Deception and Wrongdoing in Pascal’s Pensées 381 REFERENCES Adams, Robert Merrihew 1999 Finite and Infinite Goods: A Framework for Ethics. New York: Oxford University Press. Audi, Robert 2004 The Good in the Right: A Theory of Intuition and Intrinsic Value. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. Baird, Alexander William Stewart 1975 Studies in Pascal’s Ethics. The Hague: M. Nijhoff. Balthasar, Hans Urs von 1984 The Glory of the Lord, Volume 3: Studies in Theological Style: Lay Styles. Translated by Andrew Louth. San Francisco: Ignatius Press. Beitzinger, A. J. 1984 “Pascal on Justice, Force, and Law.” Review of Politics 46.2: 212–43. Bourdieu, Pierre 2000 Pascalian Meditations. Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press. Cailliet, Emile, and John C. Blankenagel, eds. 1948 Great Shorter Works of Pascal. Philadelphia, Pa.: Westminster Press. Cariou, Pierre 1993 Pascal et la casuistique. Paris: PUF. Davidson, Hugh M. 1970 The Origins of Certainty: Means and Meanings in Pascal’s Pensées. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Delehanty, Ann T. 2004 “Morality and Method in Pascal’s Pensées.” Philosophy and Literature 28: 74–88. Ferreyrolles, Gérard 2002 “Compendium sur l’imagination dans les Pensées.” Littératures classiques 45: 139–45. 1995 Les Reines du monde: L’imagination et la coutume chez Pascal. Paris: Champion. Force, Pierre 1989 Le problème herméneutique chez Pascal. Paris: Vrin. 2003 “Pascal and philosophical method.” See Hammond 2003, 216–34. Frankfurt, Harry G. 2004 The Reasons of Love. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. fellow at the Center for Philosophy of Religion, University of Notre Dame. I would like to thank Karin Meyers and Lea Schweitz for reading a very early draft and making invaluable suggestions. Thanks, as well, to Franklin I. Gamwell, Paul J. Griffiths, Kathryn Tanner, and two anonymous reviewers for this journal. 382 Journal of Religious Ethics van Frassen, Bas C. 1988 “The Peculiar Effects of Love and Desire.” In Brian McLaughlin and Amelie Rorty, edited by Perspectives on Self-Deception, 123– 56. Berkeley, Calif.: University of California Press. Gadamer, Hans Georg 1989 Truth and Method. 2nd revised ed. New York: Crossroad. Gouhier, Henri 1986 Blaise Pascal: Conversion et apologétique. Paris: Vrin. Haidt, Jonathan 2001 “The Emotional Dog and Its Rational Tail: A Social Intuitionist Approach to Moral Judgment.” Psychological Review 108: 814–34. Haidt, Jonathan, and Fredrik Bjorklund 2008 “Social Intuitionists Answer Six Questions about Moral Psychology.” In Moral Psychology, Volume 2, The Cognitive Science of Morality: Intuition and Diversity, edited by W. S. Armstrong, 181–218. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Hammond, Nicholas 2003 The Cambridge Companion to Pascal. New York: Cambridge University Press. Hibbs, Thomas 2005 “Habits of the Heart: Pascal and the Ethics of Thought.” International Philosophical Quarterly 45.2: 203–20. Jones, Matthew L. 2001 “Writing and Sentiment: Blaise Pascal, the Vacuum, and the Pensées.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 32.1: 139–81. Kearney, Richard 1995 Poetics of Modernity: Toward a Hermeneutic Imagination. Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press. 2003 Strangers, Gods, and Monsters : Interpreting Otherness. New York: Routledge. Lazzeri, Christian 1993 Force et justice dans la politique de Pascal. Paris: PUF. Lear, Jonathan 1998 Love and Its Place in Nature: A Philosophical Interpretation of Freudian Psychoanalysis. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press. Levi, Anthony 1964 French Moralists: The Theory of the Passions 1585–1649. New York: Oxford University Press. Levi, Honor, ed. and trans. 1995 Pensées and Other Writings. New York: Oxford University Press. Lyons, John D. 2005 Before Imagination: Embodied Thought from Montaigne to Rousseau. Stanford, Calif: Stanford University Press. Self-Deception and Wrongdoing in Pascal’s Pensées 383 Lyotard, Jean François 1994 Lessons on the Analytic of the Sublime: Kant’s Critique of Judgment, Sections 23–29. Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press. Magnard, Pierre 1991 Pascal: La Clé Du Chiffre. Paris: Editions Universitaires. Maguire, Matthew W. 2006 The Conversion of Imagination: From Pascal through Rousseau to Tocqueville. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press. Mele, Alrfred R. 2001 Self-Deception Unmasked. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. Melzer, Sara E. 1986 Discourses of the Fall: A Study of Pascal’s Pensées. Berkeley, Calif.: University of California Press. Mesnard, Jean 1988 “Le Thème des trois orderes dan l’organisation des Pensées.” In Pascal: Thèmatique des Pensées, edited by M. Lane and Ian M. Richmond Heller, 29–56. Paris: Vrin. Miel, Jan 1969 Pascal and Theology. Baltimore, Md.: Johns Hopkins Press. Moriarty, Michael 2003a Early Modern French Thought: The Age of Suspicion. New York: Oxford University Press. 2003b “Grace and religious belief in Pascal.” See Hammond 2003, 144–61. 2006 Fallen Nature, Fallen Selves: Early Modern French Thought II. New York: Oxford University Press. Nado, Jennifer, Daniel Kelly, and Stephen Stich n.d. “Moral Judgments.” In Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Psychology, edited by John Symons and Paco Calvo. New York: Routledge. Norman, Buford 1988 Portraits of Thought: Knowledge, Methods, and Styles in Pascal. Columbus, Ohio: Ohio State University Press. Parish, Richard 2003 “Pascal’s Lettres provinciales: from flippancy to fundamentals.” See Hammond 2003, 182–200. Pascal, Blaise 1967 Provincial Letters. Translated by A. J. Krailsheimer. New York: Penguin Books. 1995 Pensées. Translated by A. J. Krailsheimer. New York: Penguin Books. 2005 Pensées. Translated by Roger Ariew. Indianapolis, Ind.: Hackett. Ross, W. D. 1930 The Right and the Good. Oxford: Clarendon. 384 Journal of Religious Ethics Sellier, Philippe 1970 Pascal et Saint Augustin. Paris: A. Colin. Sommers, Tamler 2005 “Jonathan Haidt.” The Believer 3.6 (August): 71–85. Warner, Martin 1989 Philosophical Finesse: Studies in the Art of Rational Persuasion. New York: Oxford University Press. Wetsel, David 1981 L’écriture Et Le Reste: The Pensées of Pascal in the Exegetical Tradition of Port-Royal. Columbus, Ohio: Ohio State University Press. Wolf, Susan 2002 “The True, the Good, and the Lovable: Frankfurt’s Avoidance of Objectivity.” In Contours of Agency: Essays on Themes from Harry Frankfurt, edited by Sarah Buss and Lee Overton, 227–34. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Purchase answer to see full attachment

Description: https://www.studypool.com/img/discuss/honorcode-new.png

OUR ORDER DATABASE

With over 10 years in the online academic market, we have accumulated thousands of previously completed questions and answers across the globe. You can gain access to them for a very small fee.

Want to complete your own work?